Abstract:
It is no secret that understanding of the phenomenon of cognition
in the history of philosophy has never been uniform. It is
clear that understanding of the nature of cognition, its meaning and
value was quite diff erent, let’s say in the antic epoch or the Middle
Ages than it is in our times when science has become an immediate
productive power and, accordingly, the aim of the cognitive activity
is determined by the production of material goods. Nowadays the
problems that science has to solve are posed by factories and laboratories.
But for Aristotle, one of the most prominent philosophers
of Antiquity, philosophy is the supreme among all sciences since it
is free. It means that it is not determined by anything and has the
end of its existence in itself. Contemplation of the fi rst causes and
principles is prior to all other activities. According to Aristotle, it is a
supreme activity. That is why it is impossible to place any other science
above philosophical cognition since the most divine is the most valuable as well. Aristotle concludes that all other sciences are more
necessary than philosophy though none is better and more valuable
than it (Aristotle, 1976:70) Thus, according to Aristotle, a contemplative
attitude to reality is valuable in itself. It has in itself the
instance that justifi es it and attaches the meaning to it. Therefore,
the signifi cance of the theoretical work for man is determined not
by the truth itself or, as later Spinoza will say, intellectual love for
God. In this sense, it is a real entelechy (“entelechy” means having
the end in itself). In this respect, the Aristotelian interpretation of
cognition as an activity which has its end in itself and is of the original
value opposes the understanding of the cognition formulated in
the New Times by Francis Bacon. According to Bacon, knowledge is
power, therefore the value of the cognitive activity is determined by
the practical-utilitarian results ensuing from it, namely, such a result
is man’s domination over the forces of nature.
A quite diff erent interpretation of the essence of cognition is
given by Heraclitus of Ephesus. According to him, cognition of an
event means understanding the place of this event in the universal
unity of the world and the relation of this unity to Logos. That is why
Heraclitus says that the mark of wisdom is to be in consent not with
him, but with Logos and to understand that everything is in unity
since there is only one wisdom – to use everything to conceive the
essence which constitutes all things in the world (Anthology of the
world Philosophy, 1969:279).
Wisdom and knowledge imply the relation to this unity and retaining
it. Therefore, the matter is not how much we know but whether
we know the One that rules the universal unity of the things and
phenomena in the world. Therefore, it is evident that Heraclitus
understands cognition in his own way and needs much more from
cognition than a mere description of its factual and immediate presence
or even determining its closest causes. Heraclitus who relies
on such a deep conception of cognition would, of course, have never
admitted that the present-day scientifi c interpretation of cognition is cognition. It is not just a historical-chronological limitation of
Heraclitus’s interpretation of cognition that matters, but a diff erent
understanding of the concept of cognition, and the existence of different
world outlook models of cognition. Thus, for example, present-
day botany off ers us certain knowledge on ivy or a pomegranate
tree. In particular, it describes the morphological structure of these
plants (e.g., ivy is characterized by a mosaic arrangement of leaves,
etc.), and states the biological regularities of their functioning and
vital activities. But botany as long as we remain within the limits of
this science will fail to explain why the united world being displayed
itself as a vegetal being and, in its turn, why the vegetal being is
displayed in the modus of ‘ivy’ or ‘a pomegranate fl ower’. This eventually
is to be explained by philosophy which certainly will have to
consider the data obtained by botany or any other special science.
It is certain that Heraclitus relying on his specifi c understanding of
cognition would not be satisfi ed with the data concerning plants given
by botany only. Even more, he would never have considered it a
“cognition”.
In our epoch of unprecedented development of science M.
Heidegger stated that science does not think (die wissenschaft denkt
nicht) (Heidegger M. 1971:4). Later Heidegger interpreted this, at the
fi rst sight, paradoxical statement when said that the phrase “science
does not think” means that science does not move in the dimension
of philosophy. He thinks that science remains in the sphere of an
existing or the unity of existings and never manages to enter the
sphere of the being. Therefore, it has nothing to do with the conceptualization
of the being. “Thinking”/ cognition in its genuine sense is
the task of poetry and philosophy and not of science since the basis
of science is in the development of the contemporary technique and
not vice versa (Heidegger M. 1970:72).
Therefore, as we can see, it is possible to speak about various
understandings of the concept of cognition in the great systems of
the theory of cognition throughout the whole history of gnosiology. Thus, for example, cognition as comprehension of the meaning, the
“logos” of the universal unity of the world is given by Heraclitus, cognition
as remembering or reminiscence is found at Plato, cognition
as constituting the object of cognition in the process of cognition
– at Kant, cognition as admitting theoretical value – at Rickert, cognition
as self-revealing of the being and existing in it – in existentialism,
cognition as a refl ection of the regularities of the objective
reality in order to transform it – in the Marxist gnosiology, etc. These
interpretations of the concept of cognition, of course, form a certain
unity without which there could be no united history of cognitive
theoretical thinking.